Studies in Phenomenology



Article/Publication Details
Views: 4612


NICOLAS DE WARREN “HUSSERL AND THE PROMISE OF TIME:
SUBJECTIVITY IN TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY”
Cambridge University Press, 2009. ISBN 978-0-521-87679-7

Title in the language of publication: РЕЦЕНЗИЯ НА КНИГУ Н. ДЕ ВАРРЕНА
“HUSSERL AND THE PROMISE OF TIME:
SUBJECTIVITY IN TRANSCENDENTAL PHENOMENOLOGY”
Cambridge University Press, 2009. ISBN 978-0-521-87679-7
Author: Sergei Nikonenko
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 6, №1 (2017), 272-280
Language: Russian
Document type: Review
PDF (Downloads: 3268)

Abstract
The review considers the clue aspects of the book. De Warren makes the main subject of research Husserl’s idea of subjectivity in relation to the problem of time-consciousness. Husserl’s system itself the author refers to the subjective idealism. Husserl’s subjectivity is treated as the constitution of the world in time-consciousness. De Warren tries to argue that the idea of temporality is important for Husserl’s understanding of the identity of the subject. Conducting a comparative analysis of the ideas of Husserl and Brentano, de Warren shows that Husserl was the first who achieved in phenomenology a clear understanding of the experience. Criticizing the views of Derrida, de Warren argues that Husserl insists on the definition of I as a self-sufficient subject in spite of the importance of the problem of Other. One of the main conclusions of the book is the following: the subject is the history of the constitutional exercise of his own temporality. But it is a matter for further discussions. In the opinion of the reviewer this conclusion seemed to be controversial, but it doesn’t reduce the impression of a fundamental, profound and subtle analysis of the phenomenological ideas of time and subjectivity.

Key words
Phenomenology, Husserl, subjectivity, time, consciousness, understanding.

References

  • Brentano, F. (1996). Izbrannye raboty [Selected Texts]. Moscow: Intellectual Book House. (in Russian).
  • Derrida, Zh. (2000). O grammatologii [On Grammatology]. Moscow: Ad Marginem. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (1999). Idei k chistoy fenomenologii i fenomenologicheskoy filosofii [Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy]. Moscow: Intellectual Book House. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (2011). Logicheskie issledovania, t. 1 [Logical Investigations. Vol. I]. Moscow: Akademical Project. (in Russian).
  • Khaidegger, M. (1997). Bytie i vremya [Being and Time]. Moscow: Ad Marginem. (in Russian).
  • De Warren, N. (2009). Husserl and the Promise of Time: Subjectivity in Transcendental Phenomenology. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 6104


EMPLOTMENT AND THERAPEUTIC INTERACTION:
PHENOMENOLOGICAL MOTIVES IN MEDICAL ANTHROPOLOGY OF CHERYL MATTINGLY

Title in the language of publication: EMPLOTMENT И ТЕРАПЕВТИЧЕСКОЕ ВЗАИМОДЕЙСТВИЕ:
ФЕНОМЕНОЛОГИЧЕСКИЕ МОТИВЫ В МЕДИЦИНСКОЙ АНТРОПОЛОГИИ ЧЕРИЛ МАТТИНГЛИ
Author: Vitaly Lekhtsier
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 6, №1 (2017), 140-160
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2017-6-1-140-160 PDF (Downloads: 3774)

Abstract
This article focuses on the phenomenological aspects of Cheryl Mattingly’s empirical research. Cheryl Mattingly is one of the brightest representatives of modern American medical anthropology. Medical anthropology – actively developing social science – often, especially since the end of the 80-ies of the last century, refers to the conceptual resources of phenomenological philosophy to justify their methodological and value priorities. Such reference is connected with the attention of medical anthropologists to the subjective experience of illness and health, to the meaning of suffering, to patients’ storytelling, to situational effects of clinical interactions, to the changes in the life-world of man caused by serious chronic diseases. The first part of the article explicates the theoretical framework of the version of the applied phenomenology, which is offered by Mattingly in her long-term research conducted in 1990s and 2000 years. The subject of these research works was clinical interactions between occupational therapists and their patients. The analysis of these interactions is based on Paul Ricoeur’s phenomenologically grounded thesis that between the narrative and the experience of time there is an isomorphism thanks to the binding force of the plot. Mattingly brings the concept of narrative and a series of accompanying characteristics from the sphere of philosophical narratology to the sphere of phenomenology of (inter)action. The main idea of Mattingly is that the action itself has a narrative structure, – in the sense that actors themselves perform emplotment of interaction, configure the current events in a way that they are built into a whole, namely therapeutic history in which each successive episode of therapy follows from the previous one. The second part of the article illustrates on example of real therapy session how these ideas work in practice, in the process of the interpretation of particular therapeutic interactions. In general, we are planning to show that, although Mattingly’s appeal to phenomenological context is not systematic, and it is more correct to speak of the phenomenological “motives” in her work, it can be treated as one of the most interesting applications of phenomenological philosophy in the field of social sciences.

Key words
Therapeutic interaction, narrative, practice, time, experience, phenomenology, emplotment.

References

  • Arendt, H. (2000). Vita activa, ili o deyatel’noi zhizni [Vita Activa or an Active Life]. St. Petersburg: Aleteiya. (in Russian).
  • Benner, P. (1984). From Novice to Expert: Excellence and Power in Clinical Nursing Practice. Menlo Park, CA: Addison-Wesley.
  • Benner, P. (1985). Quality of Life: A Phenomenological Perspective on Explanation, Prediction, and Understanding in Nursing Science. Advances in Nursing Science, 8 (1), 1–14.
  • Benner, P. (1994). The Tradition and Skill of Interpretive Phenomenology in Studying Health, Illness, and Caring Practices. In P. Benner (Ed.), Interpretive Phenomenology: Embodiment, Caring, and Ethics in Health and Illness (99–126). Thousand Oaks, London, New Delhi: Sage Publication.
  • Brooks, P. (1984). Reading for the Plot. Design and Intention in Narrative. New York: Vintage Books.
  • Chan, G., Brykczynski, K., Malone, R., Benner, P. (Eds.). (2010). Interpretive Phenomenology in Health Care Research. Indianapolis, IA: Sigma Theta Tau International.
  • Ember, C. R., Ember, M. (Eds.) (2004). Encyclopedia of Medical Anthropology. V. 1, V. 2. New York, Boston, Dordrecht, London, Moscow: Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers.
  • Fleming, M. A (1993). Common Sense Practice in an Uncommon World. Clinical Reasoning: Forms of Inquiry in Therapeutic Practice. Philadelphia: F.A. Davis Press.
  • Foster, G.M., & Anderson, B.G. (1978). Medical Anthropology. New York: Wiley.Frank, A. (1997). Wounded Storyteller: Body, Illness, and Ethics. Chicago, London: University Of Chicago Press.
  • Frye, N. (1957). Anatomy of Criticism: Four Essays. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Good, B.J. (1994a). Medicine, Rationality, and Experience. An Anthropological Perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Good, B.J. (1994b). A Body in Pain — The Making of a World of Chronic Pain. In M.-J. DelVecchio-Good, P. E. Brodwin, B. J. Good, A. Kleinman (Eds.), Pain as Human Experience: An Anthropological Perspective (29–48). California: Berkeley, Los Angeles; London: University of California Press.
  • Good, M.-J.D., Munakata, T., Kobayashi, Y., Mattingly, C., Good, B.J. (1994). Oncology and Narrative Time. Social Science & Medicine, 38 (6), 855–862. doi: 10.1016/0277-9536(94)90157-0
  • Gusserl’, E. (1999). Idei k chistoi fenomenologii i fenomenologicheskoi filosofii T.1 [Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. V. 1]. Moscow: House of Intellectual Book. (in Russian).
  • Kleinman, A. (1988). The Illness Narratives. Suffering, Healing, and the Human Condition. New York: Basic Books.
  • Kleinman, A., Das, V., Lock, M. (Eds.) (I997). Introduction. In Social Suffering (IX-XXVI). Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Lekhtsier, V. (2010). Fenomenologicheskie osnovaniya meditsinskoi antropologii [Phenomenological Basics of Medical Anthropology]. Logos, 5 (78), 183–195. (in Russian).
  • Mattingly, C. (1991a). The Narrative Nature of Clinical Reasoning. The American Journal of Occupational Therapy, 45 (11), 998–1005. doi:10.5014/ajot.45.11.998
  • Mattingly, C. (1991b). What is Clinical Reasoning? The American Journal of Occupational Therapy, 45 (11), 979–986. doi:10.5014/ajot.45.11.979
  • Mattingly, C., & Fleming, M.H. (1994a). Clinical Reasoning: Forms of Inquiry in a Therapeutic Practice. Philadelphia, PA: F.A. Davis Company.
  • Mattingly, C. (1994b). The Concept of Therapeutic “Emplotment”. Social Science & Medicine, 38 (6), 811–822. doi: 10.1016/0277-9536(94)90153-8
  • Mattingly, C. (1998). Healing Dramas and Clinical Plots: The Narrative Structure of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mattingly, C. (2010). The Paradox of Hope: Journeys through a Clinical Borderland. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press.
  • Mihel’, D. (2010a). Meditsinskaya antropologiya: istoriya razvitiya distsipliny [Medical Anthropology: the History of the Development of the Discipline]. Saratov: Techno-Decor. (in Russian).
  • Mihel’, D. (2010b). Sotsial’naya antropologiya meditsinskikh sistem: meditsinskaya antropologiya [Social Anthropology of Medical Systems: Medical Anthropology]. Saratov: New Project. (in Russian).
  • Mihel’, D. (2013). Izuchaya kul’turu, zdorov’e i bolezn’: meditsinskaya antropologiya kak oblast’ znaniya [Studying Culture, Health and Illness: Medical Anthropology as a Field of Knowledge]. Bulletin of SSTU, 2 (70), 206–217. (in Russian).
  • Mitchell, T. J.W. (1980). On Narrative. Critical Inquiry, 7 (1), 1–4.
  • Ricoeur, P. (1980). Narrative time. Critical Inquiry, 7 (1), 169–190.
  • Rikjor, P. (1998). Vremya i rasskaz. T. 1 [Time and Narrative. V.1]. Moscow, St. Petersburg: University Book. (in Russian).
  • Roney, J.G. (1959). Medical Anthropology: A Synthetic Discipline. The New Physician, 8 (1), 32–33.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 5043


LANGUAGE, DESCRIPTION AND NECESSITY. WAS WITTGENSTEIN’S PHENOMENOLOGY A HUSSERLIAN PHENOMENOLOGY?

Title in the language of publication: LANGUAGE, DESCRIPTION AND NECESSITY. WAS WITTGENSTEIN’S PHENOMENOLOGY A HUSSERLIAN PHENOMENOLOGY?
Author: Michał Piekarski
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 6, №1 (2017), 45-57
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2017-6-1-45-57 PDF (Downloads: 3659)

Abstract
In this article we would like to prove that the so-called Ludwig Wittgenstein’s phenomenology was not the phenomenology in Husserlian sense. Ludwig Wittgenstein’s thought is most often associated with analytical philosophy, pragmatism or a specific metaphilosophical programme. Conversely, the philosopher is rarely considered as belonging to the phenomenological school. What remains problematic is whether 1) Wittgenstein did in fact practice some form of phenomenology and, if so, 2) what school of thought should it be related to? Both problems may be brought down to one basic question of 3) what is phenomenology? The answer to this last question, albeit tentative, will help us answer questions one and two. We can give a preliminary answer to our third question. We could say the following: phenomenology is a method to describe what is given for description and how it is given in terms of analysing the conditions under which an object may appear. As such, it is a transcendental way to encapsulate conditions determining the possibility of any experience. We may ask now whether Wittgenstein was a phenomenologist by this definition of phenomenology. If we conclude that he was not, we will try to answer our second question – can we talk of Wittgenstein’s phenomenology in any other sense, much as we do in the case of phenomenologies of Mach, Einstein or Austin. Ludwig Wittgenstein used the word phenomenology to describe his philosophy twice. First, in his notes from 1929 which later served as material for the posthumously published Philosophische Bemerkungen, and then in 1951 in a collection of notes published as Bemerkungen über die Farben. Let us consider what he wrote in 1929.

Key words
Description, grammar, Husserl, phenomenology, phenomenological language, philosophical methods, space, Wittgenstein.

References

  • Borges, J. L. (2000). Labyrinths: Selected Stories and Other Writings. London: Penguin Classics.
  • Crary, A., & Read, R. (Eds.). (2000). The New Wittgenstein. London: Routledge.
  • Dreyfus, H.L., & Hall, H. (1982). Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science. Cambrige, Mass.: M.I.T. Press.
  • Dufrenne, M. (1966). Wittgenstein et Husserl. In Jalons (188–207). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Drummond, J. (1990). Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational Realism: Noema and Object. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • Føllesdal, D. (1969). Husserl’s Notion of Noema. Journal of Philosophy, 66 (20), 680–687.
  • Galvez, J. P. (2008). Phänomenologische Probleme des Sehens, In J. P. Galvez (Ed.), Phenomenology as Grammar. Frankfurt am M.: Ontos Verlag.
  • Hintikka, J. (1996a). Die Wende der Philosophie: Wittgensteins New Logic of 1928. In Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths (79–105). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Hintikka, J. (1996b). The Idea of Phenomenology in Wittgenstein and Husserl. In Ludwig Wittgenstein: Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths (55–77). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Husserl, E. (1993). Logische Untersuchungen, Bd. II/2. Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Husserl, E. (1999). The Idea of Phenomenology. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer.
  • McIntyre, R., & Smith, D. W. (1982). Husserl and Intentionality: A Study of Mind, Meaning, and Language. Dordrecht, Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co.
  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of Perception. London, New York: Routledge.
  • Mohanty, J. N. (1982). Husserl and Frege: Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
  • Park, B.-C. (1998). Phenomenological Aspects of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer.
  • Piekarski M. (2015). The Problem of Realism in Andrzej Półtawski’s Phenomenology. Dialogue and Universalism, 3, 151–162.
  • Półtawski, A. (1973). Świat, spostrzeżenie, świadomość. Fenomenologiczna koncepcja świadomości a realism [World, Perception, Consciousness. Phenomenological Conception of Consciousness and Realism]. Warszawa: PWN. (in Polish).
  • Ricoeur, P. (2014). The Later Wittgenstein and the Later Husserl on Language. Ricoeur Studies, 5 (1), 28–48.
  • Schlick, M. (1925). Allgemeinen Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Springer.
  • Sokolowski, R. (1999). Introduction to Phenomenology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Spiegelberg, H. (1968). The Puzzle of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Phänomenologie (1929–?). American Philosophical Quarterly, 5 (4), 244–256.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1929). Some Remarks on Logical Form. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 9, 162–171.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1984a). Ludwig Wittgenstein und der Wiener Kreis. Gespräche, aufgezeichnet von Friedrich Waismann. In R. Rhees (Ed.), Werkausgabe Band 3. Berlin: Suhrkamp Verlag.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1984b). Philosophischen Bemerkungen. In R. Rhees (Ed.), Werkausgabe Band 2. Berlin: Suhrkamp Verlag.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1986). Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (1998–2000). Wittgenstein’s Nachlass. The Bergen Electronic Edition. Oxford: Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen.
  • Peursen, C. A. van (1959). Edmund Husserl and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 20 (2), 181–197.
  • Wright, G. H. von (1969). The Wittgenstein Papers. The Philosophical Review,78 (4), 483–503.
  • Zahavi D. (2004). Husserl’s Noema and the Internalism-Externalism Debate. Inquiry, 47(1), 42–66.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 5133


INTENTIONALITY: AN AMERICAN POINT OF VIEW.

Title in the language of publication: ИНТЕНЦИОНАЛЬНОСТЬ:АМЕРИКАНСКАЯ ТОЧКА ЗРЕНИЯ
Author: Sergei Nikonenko
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 6, №1 (2017), 9–44
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2017-6-1-9-44 PDF (Downloads: 3835)

Abstract
The matter of the article is to give an outline of American theories of intentionality and to compare it with E. Husserl’s phenomenology. It is one of the first Russian systematic studies of American theories on intentionality that is represented here. It is John Searle’s philosophy that is the main American theory of intentionality. Some other thinkers (R. Chisholm, J. Findlay, N. Rescher, E. Thompson, D.W. Smith, etc.) are studied here too. Searle treats intentionality as a natural quality of consciousness. He forbids the linguistic approach; intentionality is understood from the point of view of humanistic (internal) realism. Intentionality is successive when the subject is satisfied by his acquaintance with the object. The main feature of intentionality is aspectuality that has the subject of not eliminated subjectivity of any conscious act and the first person ontology. Searle proposes the collective intentionality that is analogous to phenomenological intersubjectivity. E. Thompson proposes the synthetic theory of intentionality that unites phenomenology, philosophy of consciousness and neural science. D.W. Smith proposes the theory of intentional context. He rejects the study of atomistic intentional acts. Husserl’s and Searle’s theories of phenomenology may be united in several main points: 1. Experience is an internal process; 2. Experience cannot be separated of aspectuality; 3. Intentionality cannot be eliminated in any conscious act; 4. The other mind can be considered only from internal point of view; 5. There is collective intentionality of mankind. There are several distinctions between Husserl and Searle: 1. Searle is an realist on intentionality, Husserl puts on an idealistic concept of it; 2. Searle considers intentionality from empirical point of view, not from the rationalist one; 3. Searle is an adept of skepticism about self, he rejects transcendental concept of cogito. But irrespective of distinctions there is convergence of analytical and phenomenological views in contemporary philosophy of consciousness.

Key words
Intentionality, phenomenology, analytical philosophy, epistemology, consciousness, subject, experience, intersubjectivity.

References

  • Chernavin, G. (2016). “Nerv” fenomenologicheskoy raboty i fundamentalniy akt filosofii [“Plexus” of Phenomenological Work and the Fundamental Act of Philosophy]. Logos, 26 (1), 68–73. (in Russian).
  • Chisholm, R.M. (1955–1956). Sentences about Believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–148.
  • Dennet, D.C. (1996). Kinds of Minds: Towards an Understanding of Consciousness. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
  • Dummett, M.A.E. (1994). Origins of Analytic Philosophy. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Findlay, J.N. (1975). Phenomenology and the Meaning of Realism. In E. Pivčević (Ed.), Phenomenology and Philosophical Understanding (143–158). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Fink, O. (2016). Problemy fenomenologii Edmunda Gusserlya [The Problem of Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenology]. Logos, 26 (1), 5–46. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (1999). Idei k chistoy fenomenologii i fenomenologicheskoy filosofii [Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy]. Moscow: Intellectual Book House. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (2005). Izbrannye raboty [Selected Texts]. Moscow: Territory of Future. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (2006). Ideya fenomenologii. Pyat’ lektsii [Ideas of Phenomenology. Five Lectures]. Saint-Petersburg: Gumanitarian Academy. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (2010). Kartezianskie meditatsii [Cartesian Meditations]. Moscow: Akademical Project. (in Russian).
  • Gusserl’, E. (2011). Logicheskie issledovania. Tom 1 [Logical Investigations. Vol. I]. Moscow: Akademical Project. (in Russian).
  • Herrmann, F.V. von (2000). Ponyatie fenomenologii u Khaideggera i Gusserlya [Heidegger’s and Husserl’s Concept of Phenomenology]. Minsk: Propilei. (in Russian).
  • Khakhalova, A. (2015). Retsenziya na knigu D. Zahavi “Self and Other. Exploring Subjectivity, Sympathy, and Shame” [Review of D. Zahavi’s Book “Self and Other. Exploring Subjectivity, Sympathy, and Shame”]. Horizon. Studies in Phenomenology, 4 (1), 314–321. (in Russian).
  • Kurennoy, V. (2012) Ustarevshaya kritika fenomenologii: po tu storonu “beskonechnogo rasputyvaniya soznaniya” [An Obsolete Critique of Phenomenology: Beyond “the Infinite Disentanglement of Consciousness”]. Logos, 26 (1), 79–88. (in Russian).
  • Manster, A. (1975). Austin’s Linguistic Phenomenology. In E. Pivčević (Ed.), Phenomenology and Philosophical Understanding (110–124). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Merlo-Ponti, M. (1999). Fenomenologiya vospriyatiya [Phenomenology of Perception]. Saint-Petersburg: Juventas, Science. (in Russian).
  • Molchanov, V.I. (2010). Transtsendental’nyi opyt i transtsendental’naya naivnost’ v “Kartezianskikh meditatsiyakh” Edmunda Gusselya [Transcendental Experience and Transcendental Naivety in Edmund Husserl’s “Cartesian Meditations”]. In E. Gusserl’, Kartezianskie meditatsii [Cartesian Meditations] (200–224). Moscow: Academical project. (in Russian).
  • Motroshilova, N.V. (1968). Printsipy i protivorechiya fenomenologicheskoi filosofii [Principles and Contradictions of Phenomenological Philosophy]. Moscow: Higher School. (in Russian).
  • Motroshilova, N.V. (2003).“Idei I” Edmunda Gusserlya kak vvedeniye v fenomenologiyu [Edmund Husserl’s “Ideas I” as an Introduction to Phenomenology]. Moscow: Phenomenology-Hermeneutics. (in Russian).
  • Patkul’, A.B. (2016). Trudnosti fenomenologichekogo issledovaniya: Fink i Gusserl’ [Difficulties of Phenomenological Research: Fink and Husserl]. Logos, 26 (1), 89–93. (in Russian).
  • Pivčević, E. (Ed.). (1975). Phenomenology and Philosophical Understanding.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Prekhtl’, P. (1999). Vvedenie v fenomenologiyu Gusserlya [Introduction to Husserl’s Phenomenology]. Tomsk: Bagpipe. (in Russian).
  • Patnem, H. (2002). Razum, istina i istoriya [Reason, Truth and History]. Moscow: Praksis. (in Russian).
  • Razeev, D.N. (2004). V setyakh fenomenologii. In E. Gusserl’ & D.N. Razeev, Vsetyakh fenomenologii. Osnovnye problemy fenomenologii [In the Phenomenological Net. Main Problems of Phenomenology]. Saint Petersburg: Saint-Petersburg University Press. (in Russian).
  • Rorty, R. (1979). The Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
  • Savin, A.O. (2015). O sushchnosti fenomenologicheskoi filosofii [On the Essence of Phenomenological Philosophy]. Horizon. Studies in Phenomenology, 4 (1), 9–37. (in Russian).
  • Searle, J.R. (1983). Intentionality. An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Searle, J.R. (2002). Consciousness and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Serl’, D. (2002). Otkryvaya soznanie zanovo [The Rediscovery of the Mind]. Moscow: Idea-Press. (in Russian).
  • Serl’, D. (2004). Ratsional’nost’ v deistvii [Rationality in Action]. Moscow: Progress-Tradition.
  • Smith, D.W. (2004). Mind World: Essays in Phenomenology and Ontology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Shpigel’berg, G. (2002). Fenomenologicheskoe dvizhenie [The Phenomenological Movement]. Moscow: Logos. (in Russian).
  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life. Biology, Phenomenology and the Science of Mind. Cambridge, Mass., London: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
  • Uaitkhed, A.N. (1990). Izbrannye raboty po filosofii [Selected Texts on Philosophy]. Moscow: Progress (in Russian).
  • Vitgenshtein, L. (1994). Filosofskiye raboty I [Philosophical Works I]. Moscow: Gnozis. (in Russian).