Studies in Phenomenology



Article/Publication Details
Views: 519


CALL FOR PROPOSAL
HORIZONS BEYOND BORDERS: ESSAYS ON THE LEGACY OF PHENOMENOLOGY IN CENTRAL AND EASTERN EUROPE IN 1945–1989

Title in the language of publication: CALL FOR PROPOSAL
HORIZONS BEYOND BORDERS: ESSAYS ON THE LEGACY OF PHENOMENOLOGY IN CENTRAL AND EASTERN EUROPE IN 1945–1989
Author: WITOLD PŁOTKA
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 13, №2 (2021), 290–292
Language: English
Document type: Call For Proposal
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2024-13-1-115–128 PDF (Downloads: 519)

Abstract
- - -

Keywords
- - -

References

    - - -

Article/Publication Details
Views: 712


INTRODUCTION

Title in the language of publication: ВСТУПИТЕЛЬНОЕ СЛОВО
Author: GARRIS ROGONYAN
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 13, №2 (2021), 9-14
Language: Russian
Document type: Introduction
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2024-13-1-9-14 PDF (Downloads: 712)

Abstract
- - -

Keywords
- - -

References

    - - -

Article/Publication Details
Views: 691


DALE JACQUETTE
ALEXIUS MEINONG, THE SHEPHERD OF NON-BEING
Moscow: Kanon + ROOI “Reabilitatsiia”, 2023. ISBN 978-5-88373-782-3

Title in the language of publication: РЕЦЕНЗИЯ НА КНИГУ Д.ЖАККЕТТА «АЛЕКСИУС МАЙНОНГ, ПАСТЫРЬ НЕ-БЫТИЯ»
Москва: Канон + РООИ «Реабилитация», 2023. ISBN 978-5-88373-782-3
Author: ANDREI PATKUL
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 13, №2 (2021), 280–289
Language: Russian
Document type: Review
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2024-13-1-280–289 PDF (Downloads: 691)

Abstract
In my review, I evaluate the first translation of Dale Jacquette’s book entitled Alexius Meinong, The Shepherd of Non-Being into Russian. First of all, I point out the relevance of the publication of this translation. It is conditioned, in my view, by the fact that the person of Alexius Meinong—one of the important representatives of the school of Franz Brentano—still remains undeservedly forgotten and not enough studied in both domestic and foreign history of philosophy. At the same time, studying the legacy of Meinong could shed the light on the peculiarity of the processes that took place in European philosophy at the turn of the 19th–20th centuries, as well as show the common sources of such divergent directions in modern philosophy as analytical philosophy and phenomenology. Moreover, philosophy of Meinong could discover some perspectives for modern thought that other philosophers of the past cannot indicate. All these points, in my opinion, are taken into account in Jacquette’s monograph. The advantage of his research is that he reconstructs the philosophy of Meinong, his theory of objects in a very broad historical and philosophical context of both phenomenological (F.Brentano, E.Husserl) and analytical (B.Russell, W.V.O.Quine, D.K.Lewis, S.Kripke) traditions. Systematically, the center of Meinong’s theory of objects is the doctrine of so-called Außersein of the objects, which can be considered not only as existing, but as not yet existing, no longer existing and even impossible. As conclusion, I criticize the translations of some of Meinong/Jacquette terms used in the monograph under review.

Keywords
Alexius Meinong, theory of objects, intentional objects, Außersein, intensionalism, extensionalism, extra-ontology.

References

  • Aristotle. (1976). Works in 4 volumes. Vol. 1. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Mysl’ Publ. (In Russian)
  • Jacquette, D. (2015). Alexius Meining, The Shepherd of Non-Being. Cham, Heidelberg, New York, Dordrecht, London: Springer.
  • Jacquette, D. (2023). Alexius Meining, The Shepherd of Non-Being. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Kanon + ROOI Reabilitatsiia Publ. (In Russian)
  • Mironov, D. (2022). Alexius Meinong’s Semantic Investigations in the Context of Brentanist Philosophy of Language. ESSE: Studies in Philosophy and Theology, 7 (1/2), 22–41. https://doi.org/10.31119/essephts.2022.7.1–2.2 (In Russian)
  • Popik, O. (2013). The Theory of Objects by A. Minong and Universal Nature of Logical Laws. Vestinik of the Plekhanov Russian University of Economics, 9 (63), 46–51. (In Russian).
  • Seliverstov, V. (2021). Alexius Meinong’s Extraontology. Beyond Being and Non-Being. Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, 58 (1), 220–234. (In Russian)
  • Vdovina, G. (2022a). Alexius Meinong’s Theory of Objects Is Looking for a Home. ESSE: Studies in Philosophy and Theology, 7 (1/2), 5–21. https://doi.org/10.31119/essephts.2022.7.1–2.1 (In Russian)
  • Vdovina, G. (2022b). The Late Scholastic Roots of Alexius Meinong’s Theory of Objects. The Philosophy Journal, 15 (1), 5–20. https://doi.org/10.21146/2072-0726-2022-15-1-5-20

Article/Publication Details
Views: 972


NORM, ONTOLOGY, CONCEPTUAL SCHEME: NORMATIVE HEIDEGGERIANISM IN PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL CONSIDERATION

Title in the language of publication: НОРМА, ОНТОЛОГИЯ, КОНЦЕПТУАЛЬНАЯ СХЕМА: НОРМАТИВНОЕ ХАЙДЕГГЕРИАНСТВО В ФИЛОСОФСКОМ И ИСТОРИЧЕСКОМ РАССМОТРЕНИИ
Author: ILIA ONEGIN
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 13, №2 (2021), 177–206
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2024-13-1-177–206 PDF (Downloads: 972)

Abstract
This article reconstructs the normative strategy of interpretation of Martin Heidegger’s Being and Time in modern analytical philosophy, and also proposes a theoretical framework for understanding this strategy as a historical phenomenon. The article describes the development of the normative direction in the interpretation of Heidegger’s fundamental ontology. Its first branch—the socio-normative, or the neopragmatist one—is associated with such philosophers as John Haugeland and Robert Brandom. The second one—the ethico-normative, or postneopragmatist one—branch is represented by Steven Crowell and Sacha Golob. It is shown that the first group of normativists focused mainly on implicit social norms and structures of conformity, while the second—focuses primarily on Kantian ethics and Christina Korsgaard’s interpretation of Kant, as well as on the inferentialist philosophy of language of Robert Brandom. The conceptual schemes used by each of the representatives of these approaches are reconstructed. The connections of different approaches within the framework of the normative direction with each other are shown. The concept of a relay race is proposed, which can describe normative Heideggerianism as a historical phenomenon. It is shown that the development of normative Heideggerianism can be characterized as theoretical progress in relation to the accuracy of the interpretation of Heidegger’s texts. The grounds for the comparative “progressiveness” of different normative approaches in the updates of the basic normative conceptual scheme that they involve are clarified. It is also shown that the progress of the normative conceptual scheme in the direction of flexibility and adaptation to Heidegger’s text is fraught with a loss of meaningfulness of the very concept of norm. It is argued that the concept of norm, despite the loss of its empirical content, can be used to translate Heidegger’s concepts for pragmatic reasons.

Keywords
Martin Heidegger, normative interpretation, neopragmatism, norm, commitment, practical identity, constitutive standard, relay race, conceptual scheme.

References

  • Bartky, S. L. (1970). Originative Thinking in the Later Philosophy of Heidegger. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 30 (3), 368–381. https://doi.org/10.2307/2105602
  • Brandom, R. B. (1976). Practice and Object (Doctoral Thesis). Princeton: Princeton University.
  • Brandom, R. B. (1983). Heidegger’s Categories in “Being and Time”. The Monist, 66 (3), 387–409. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist198366327
  • Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.
  • Brandom, R. B. (1997). Dasein, the Being That Thematizes. Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy, 5 (1/2), 1–38. https://doi.org/10.5840/epoche199751/24
  • Brandom, R. B. (2000). Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.
  • Brandom, R. B. (2002). Tales of the Mighty Dead: Historical Essays in the Metaphysics of Intentionality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Brandom, R. B. (2008). Between Saying and Doing: Towards an Analytic Pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Carnap, R. (1993). Overcoming Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language. Vestnik MGU. Filosofiia, 6, 11–26. (In Russian)
  • Cerf, S. H. (1940). An Approach to Heidegger’s Ontology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1 (2), 177–190. https://doi.org/10.2307/2102737
  • Crowell, S. G. (1981). Truth and Reflection: The Development of Transcendental Logic in Lask, Husserl, and Heidegger (Doctoral Thesis). New Haven: Yale University.
  • Crowell, S. G. (1999). Phenomenology and the Question of Being: Heidegger. In S. Glendinning (Ed.), The Edinburgh Encyclopedia of Continental Philosophy (283–295). Edinburgh: Edinburgh Uni versity Press.
  • Crowell, S. G. (2000). Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning. Paths toward Transcendental Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
  • Crowell, S. G. (2001). Subjectivity: Locating the First-Person in “Being and Time”. Inquiry, 44 (4), 433–454. https://doi.org/10.1080/002017401753263243
  • Crowell, S. G. (2007a). Conscience and Reason: Heidegger and the Grounds of Intentionality. In S. Crowell & J. Malpas (Eds.), Transcendental Heidegger (43–62). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
  • Crowell, S. G. (2007b). Sorge or Selbstbewusstsein? Heidegger and Korsgaard on the Sources of Normativity. European Journal of Philosophy, 15 (3), 315–333. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468- 0378.2007.00267.x
  • Crowell, S. G. (2008). Measure-Taking: Meaning and Normativity in Heidegger’s Philosophy. Continental Philosophy Review, 41, 261–276. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-008-9085-6
  • Crowell, S. G. (2010). Husserl’s Subjectivism: The ‘ganz einzigen Formen’ of Consciousness and the Philosophy of Mind. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, Phenomenology, Sciences: Essays in Commemoration of Edmund Husserl (363–390). Dordrecht, Heidelberg, London: Springer.
  • Crowell, S. G. (2013). Heidegger on Practical Reasoning, Morality, and Agency. In S. Crowell, Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger (282–301). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Crowell, S. G. (2017a). Competence over Being as Existing: The Indispensability of Haugeland’s Heidegger. In Z. Adams & J. Browning (Eds.), Giving a Damn Essays in Dialogue with John Haugeland (73–102). Cambridge & London: MIT Press.
  • Crowell, S. G. (2017b). Exemplary Necessity: Heidegger, Pragmatism and Reason. In O. Švec & J. Čapek (Eds.), Pragmatic Perspectives in Phenomenology (242–256). New York & Abingdon: Routledge.
  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1972). What Computers Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. New York, Evanston, San Francisco, London: Harper & Row.
  • Dzhokhadze, I. D. (2015). Robert Brandom’s Analytical Pragmatism. Moscow: IFRAN Publ. (In Russian)
  • Dzhokhadze, I. D. (2021). Neopragmatism as Lebensphilosophie. Filosofskaia mysl’, 7, 65–73. https://doi.org/10.25136/2409-8728.2021.7.36042 (In Russian)
  • Farber, M. (1958). Heidegger on the Essence of Truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 4 (18), 523–532. (In Russian)
  • Gallagher, S., & Miyahara, K. (2012). Neo-Pragmatism and Enactive Intentionality. In J. Schulkin (Ed.), Action, Perception and the Brain: Adaptation and Cephalic Expression (117–146). London: Pal- grave Macmillan.
  • Golob, S. (2014). Heidegger on Concepts, Freedom and Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Golob, S. (2020). What Does It Mean to ‘Act in the Light of ’ Norms? Heidegger and Kant on Commitments and Critique. In M. Bruch and I. McMullin (Eds.), Transcending Reason: Heidegger on Rationality (79–98). London, New York: Rowman and Littlefield International.
  • Haugeland, J. (1982). Heidegger on Being a Person. Nous, 16 (1), 15–26. https://doi.org/10.2307/2215406
  • Haugeland, J. (1985). Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • Haugeland, J. (1990a). The Intentionality All-Stars. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 383–427. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214199
  • Haugeland, J. (1990b). Dasein’s Disclosedness. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 28 (S1), 51–73. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.1990.tb00565.x
  • Haugeland, J. (1998a). Toward a New Existentialism. In J. Haugeland, Having Thoughts. Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind (1–6). Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.
  • Haugeland, J. (1998b) Truth and Rule-Following. In J. Haugeland, Having Thoughts. Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind (305–361). Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.
  • Haugeland, J. (2005). Reading Brandom Reading Heidegger. European Journal of Philosophy, 3 (13), 421–428. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2005.00237.x
  • Heidegger, M. (1967). Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.
  • Heidegger, M. (1997). Being and Time (V. V. Bibikhin, Trans.). Rus. Ed. Moscow: Ad Marginem Publ. (In Russian)
  • Heidegger, M. (1998). Prolegomena to the History of the Concept of Time (E. V. Borisov, Trans.). Rus. Ed. Tomsk: Vodolei Publ. (In Russian)
  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Being and Time (§ 31–38). In A. V. Mikhailov (Trans.), The Origin of the Work of Art (466–519). Rus. Ed. Moscow: Akademicheskii proekt Publ. (In Russian)
  • Henschen, T. (2012). Dreyfus and Haugeland on Heidegger and Authenticity. Human Studies, 35, 95–113. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-012-9212-6
  • Hildebrand, D. (2018). Dewey, Rorty, and Brandom: The Challenges of Linguistic Neopragmatism. In S. Fesmire (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Dewey (99–130). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Karnap, R. (1993). Overcoming Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language (A. V. Kezin, Trans.). Vestnik MGU. Filosofiia, 6, 11–26. (In Russian)
  • Koopman, C. (2007). Language Is a Form of Experience: Reconciling Classical Pragmatism and Neopragmatism. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 43 (4), 694–727. https://doi.org/10.1353/csp.2007.0054
  • Korsgaard, C. M. (1996). The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Olafson, F. A. (1987). Heidegger and the Philosophy of Mind. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Pris, I. E. (2014). Heidegger’s Quantum Phenomenology. Filosofskaia mysl’, 4, 46–67. https://doi.org/10.7256/2306-0174.2014.4.11625 (In Russian)
  • Pris, I. E. (2021). Anxiety, Authenticity, and the Structure of Rationality. Rus. Ed. Filosofiia nauki, 2 (89), 44–68. https://doi.org/10.15372/PS20210204 (In Russian)
  • Rorty, R. (1976). Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey. The Review of Metaphysics, 2 (30), 280–305.
  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Rorty, R., Vattimo, G., & Zabala, S. (2008). What is Religion’s Future after Metaphysics? Logos, 4 (67), 93–110. (In Russian)
  • Ryle, G. (1929). Sein und Zeit by Martin Heidegger. Mind, 38 (151), 355–370.
  • Ryle, G. (2009). Review of Martin Farber: ‘The Foundations of Phenomenology’. In Critical Papers. Vol. 1. Critical Essays (223–232). London & New York: Routledge.
  • Sluga, H. (1993). Heidegger’s Crisis: Philosophy and Politics in Nazi Germany. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Wittgenstein, L. (2003). On the Character of Disquiet. In F. Waismann (Ed.), The Voices of Wittgenstein: The Vienna Circle (68–76). London & New York: Routledge.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 1049


HUSSERL, AJDUKIEWICZ, AND BLAUSTEIN ON MEANING

Title in the language of publication: HUSSERL, AJDUKIEWICZ, AND BLAUSTEIN ON MEANING
Author: DANIELE NUCCILLI, RAFAŁ LEWANDOWSKI
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 13, №2 (2021), 95–114
Language: English
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2024-13-1-95–114 PDF (Downloads: 1049)

Abstract
The aim of this article is to investigate the reception of Husserl’s theory of meaning by Ajdukiewicz and Blaustein, two members of the analytically-oriented Lvov-Warsaw School, who, in different ways, were attracted to and confronted with Husserl’s phenomenology. The discussed hypothesis is that Ajdukiewicz’s interpretation of Logical Investigations, and his original theory of meaning influenced both Blaustein’s critical reading of Husserl’s theory of intentionality and his account of meaning-intention. After outlining the central elements of “First Logical Investigation” the paper shows how it is interpreted by Ajdukiewicz in his Lvov lectures on logic and in his directival theory of meaning. What emerges is a psychological-descriptive interpretation of Husserl’s concept of meaning, and a reconsideration of his theory of intentionality within the inferential structure of beliefs in premises that motivates a person who speaks a language to believe in conclusions of a certain form. This leads Ajdukiewicz to his own original conventionalist account of meaning which is based on the identification of three main directives of meaning that represent the matrix of a given language, i.e., the grid in which each meaning finds its place. These elements allow one to demonstrate how Ajdukiewicz’s interpretation resonates in Blaustein’s critique of Husserl in his early writings, where, in addition to a psychological-descriptive reading of phenomenology we also find a conventionalist conception of meaning acts and signitive presentations. According to Blaustein, a sign can represent an object only through the conventions arising from the directives of meaning that belong to a given natural language.

Keywords
Husserl, Ajdukiewicz, Blaustein, Meaning, Phenomenology, Intentionality, Directival Theory of Meaning, Lvov–Warsaw School.

References

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1935). Der logistische Antiirrationalismus in Polen. Erkenntnis, 5, 151–164.
  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1978). The Scientific World-Perspective and Other Essays (1931-1963). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1993). Kategorie syntaktyczne i antynomie logiczne. Filozofia Nauki, 1 (1), 163-184.
  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (2014). Wykłady Kazimierza Ajdukiewicza z semantyki logicznej w Uniwersytecie Jana Kazimierza we Lwowie w roku akademickim 1930/1931. Filozofia Nauki, 22 (1), 143–158.
  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (2017). Konspekt wykładów z logiki wygłoszonych na Uniwersytecie Jana Kazimierza we Lwowie w roku akademickim 1924/1925 sporządzony przez Stefana Ołeksiuka. Filozofia Nauki, 25 (2), 137–159.
  • Blaustein, L. (1928). Husserlowska nauka o akcie, treści i przedmiocie przedstawienia. Lvov: Nakładem Towarzystwa Naukowego.
  • Blaustein, L. (1928/1929). Próba krytycznej oceny fenomenologii. Ruch Filozoficzny, 11, 164b–166b.
  • Blaustein, L. (1931). O przedstawieniach schematycznych i symbolicznych. Badania z pogranicza psychologji i estetyki. Lvov: Nakładem Przeglądu Humanistycznego.
  • Byrne, T. (2020). Ingarden’s Husserl: A Critical Assessment of the 1915 Review of the Logical Investigations. Horizon. Studies in Phenomenology, 9 (2), 513–531. https://doi.org/10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-2-513-531
  • Coniglione, F. (2010). Realtà e astrazione. Scuola polacca ed epistemologia post-positivista. Roma: Bonanno.
  • Dummett, M. (2014). Origins of Analytical Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
  • Głombik, C. (2005). Die Polen und die Göttinger phänomenologische Bewegung. Husserl Studies, 21, 1–15.
  • Grabarczyk, P. (2019). Directival Theory of Meaning. From Syntax and Pragmatics to Narrow Linguistic Content. Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Hopp, W. (2020). Phenomenology: A Contemporary Introduction. New York: Routledge.
  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical Investigations. Vol. I–II (J. N. Findlay, Trans.). London and New York: Routledge.
  • Ingarden, R. (1992). Einführung in die Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls: Osloer Vorlesungen 1967 (GW, Bd. 4). Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
  • Lewandowski, R. (2021). Prawda, jej aspekty ontologiczne i idea intelektu nieskończonego w ‘Badaniach logicznych’ Edmunda Husserla. Roczniki Filozoficzne, 69 (4), 83–124. http://doi.org/10.18290/rf21694-5
  • Maciaszek, J. (2022). Ingarden and Ajdukiewicz on Meaning. Similar Inspiration, Different Solutions. In A. Brożek & J. Jadacki (Eds.), Intuition and Analysis Roman Ingarden and the School of Kazimierz Twardowski (163–191). Krakow: Copernicus Center Press.
  • Marsonet, M. (1986). Linguaggio e conoscenza. Milano: Franco Angeli.
  • Mill, J. S. (1978). A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
  • Olech, A. (2015). Ajdukiewicz and Husserl on the Issue of the Meaning of Expressions. Studia Semiotyczne, XXIV, 130–154.
  • Płotka, W. (2017). Early Phenomenology in Poland (1895–1945): Origins, Development, and Break Down. Studies in East European Thought, 69, 79–91. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-017-9274-0
  • Płotka, W. (2020a). From Psychology to Phenomenology (and Back Again): A Controversy over the Method in the School of Twardowski. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 19 (1), 141–167. https://doi.org10.1007/s11097-019-09620-x
  • Płotka, W. (2020b). Leopold Blaustein’s Descriptive Psychology and Aesthetics in Light of His Criticism of Husserl. In W. Płotka & P. Eldridge (Eds.), Early Phenomenology in Central and Eastern Europe: Main Figures, Ideas, and Problems (163–185). Cham: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3- 030-39623-7_10
  • Płotka, W. (2021). A Critical Analysis of Blaustein’s Polemic Against Husserl’s Method. Husserl Studies, 37, 249–270. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-021-09292-z
  • Płotka, W. (2023a). Ingarden and Blaustein on Image Consciousness. Studia Phaenomenologica, 23, 89–114, https://doi.org/10.5840/studphaen2023235
  • Płotka, W. (2023b). The Origins and Development of Leopold Blaustein’s Descriptive Psychology: An Essay in the Heritage of the Lvov–Warsaw School. History of Psychology, 26 (4), 372–390. https://doi.org/10.1037/hop0000241
  • Pokropski, M. (2015), Leopold Blaustein’s Critique of Husserl’s Early Theory of Intentional Act, Object and Content. Studia Phaenomenologica, 15, 93–103. https://doi.org/10.5840/studphaen2015156
  • Searle, J. R. (2002). Consciousness and Language. Cambridge (UK): Cambridge University Press.
  • Smith, D. W., & McIntyre, R. (1982). Husserl and Intentionality. A Study of Mind, Meaning and Language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  • Szylewicz, A. (1993). Roman Ingarden’s Review of the Second Edition of Husserl’s ‘Logical Investigations’. Husserl Studies, 10 (1), 1–2. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01420545
  • Tugendhat, E. (1982). Traditional and Analytical Philosophy. Lectures on the Philosophy of Language (A. Gorner, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Willard, D. (1984). Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge. A Study in Husserl’s Early Philosophy. Ohio: Ohio University Press.
  • Woleński, J. (1989a). Logic and Philosophy in the Lvov–Warsaw School. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Woleński, J. (1989b). The Lvov-Warsaw School and the Vienna Circle. In K. Szaniawski (Ed.), The Vienna Circle and the Lvov–Warsaw School (443–453). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Woleński, J. (2017). How to Speak About History of Analytic Philosophy. In A. Brożek, F. Stadler & J. Woleński (Eds.), The Significance of the Lvov-Warsaw School in the European Culture (15–27). Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Wójcicki, R. (1999). Ajdukiewicz. Teoria znaczenia. Warsaw: Prószyński i Ska.
  • Wybraniec-Skardowska, U. (2018). Introduction. The School: Its Genesis, Development and Signifi Cance. In Á. Garrido & U. Wybraniec-Skardowska (Eds.), The Lvov–Warsaw School. Past and Present (3–14). Cham: Birkhäuser.
  • Zahavi, D. (1992). Intentionalität und Konstitution. Eine Einführung in Husserls Logische Untersuchungen. Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum Press.

Article/Publication Details
Views: 780


SINN AND ITS SHADOW. TERMINOLOGICAL ANALYSIS OF HUSSERL’S CONCEPTION OF NOETIC-NOEMATIC STRUCTURES OF PURE CONSCIOUSNESS

Title in the language of publication: СМЫСЛ И ЕГО ТЕНЬ. ТЕРМИНОЛОГИЧЕСКИЙ АНАЛИЗ ГУССЕРЛЕВСКОЙ КОНЦЕПЦИИ НОЭТИКО-НОЭМАТИЧЕСКИХ СТРУКТУР ЧИСТОГО СОЗНАНИЯ
Author: VICTOR MOLCHANOV
Issue: HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology.
Vol. 13, №2 (2021), 207–240
Language: Russian
Document type: Research Article
DOI : 10.21638/2226-5260-2024-13-1-207–240 PDF (Downloads: 780)

Abstract
The methodological premise of the investigation is the meta-difference between foreground and background as a necessary element of any difference, including the difference between conceptual and terminological types of analysis of philosophical texts. The topic of terminological analysis is the function of the terms that make up the framework of concepts, the methods and justifications for their introduction. The role of D.Hume, who was the first to draw attention to the difference in the meaning of the same word in natural and philosophical languages, is noted. More general questions are formulated regarding the prerequisites of terminological analysis: what is a term, what experience underlies the very process of introducing terms, are terms a necessary building material of philosophical texts or a necessary evil? The prerequisites for terminological analysis include the differences between a term and a word, as well as a term and a metaphor. Husserl’s concept of noetic-noematic structures is considered in terms of the difference between conceptual and terminological dimensions. The research focuses on the functions of “sense” as an intermediary between natural language and philosophical terminology. The prerequisites for the introduction of the terms “noesis” and “noema” are identified; in the first case, this is the traditional scheme of hylomorphism, in the second, the postulate of the identity of what is perceived during normal and abnormal perception. A comparison is made between Husserl’s expression “sense does not burn” with M.Bulgakov’s aphorism “manuscripts do not burn.” Husserl’s division of two types of consciousness (positional and neutral or shadow) reveals the incorrectness of Husserl’s description of the difference between the foreground and background of perception. Husserl’s description of “neutralization” is subjected to critical analysis using the example of the perception of Durer’s engraving. The final section of the article examines attempts to correlate the meaning of the word “sense” with experience, compares the role of the terms “sense” and “concept,” and also analyzes Husserl’s “generalization of the idea of meaning,” or expansion of the meaning of the term “sense.” Finally, a distinction is made between a methodology of separation, which corresponds to the boundary-setting function of terms, and a methodology of differentiation of differences, which implies the differentiating function of terms.

Keywords
noesis, noema, experience, term, quotation marks, sense, perception, hallucination.

References

  • Bateson, G. (2000). Steps to an Ecology of Mind. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Smysl Publ. (In Russian)
  • Heidegger, M. (1976). Sein und Zeit (GA 2). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klosterman.
  • Heidegger, M. (1994). Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs (GA 20). Frankfurt am Main: Vitto- rio Klosterman.
  • Heidegger, M. (1998). History of the Concept of Time: Prolegomena. Rus. Ed. Tomsk: Vodolei Publ. (In Russian)
  • Husserl, E. (1952). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie III: Die Phänomenologie und die Fundamente der Wissenschaft (Hua V). Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1975). Logische Untersuchungen. Bd. I (Hua XVIII). Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch (Hua III/I). Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen. Bd. II/1 (Hua XIX/1). Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Husserl, E. (2009). Ideas to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Book I (A. Michailov, Trans.). Rus. Ed. Moscow: Akademicheskii proekt Publ. (In Russian)
  • Husserl, E. (2011a). Logical Investigations. Vol. 1 (E. Bernstein, Trans.). Rus. Ed. Moscow: Akademicheskii proekt Publ. (In Russian)
  • Husserl, E. (2011b). Logical Investigations. Vol 2 (V. Molchanov, Trans.). Rus. Ed. Moscow: Akademicheskii proekt Publ. (In Russian)
  • Molchanov, V. (2022). Problems with the Problem of Consciousness. Abstractions and Pseudo-abstractions. Filosofskii zhurnal, 15/3, 5–20. (In Russian)
  • Motroshilova, N. (2003). Husserl’s “Ideas I” as an Introduction to Phenomenology. Moscow: Fenomenologiia-Germenevtika Publ. (In Russian)
  • Porshnev, B. (2010). Couter-suggestion and History. Historical Psychology and Sociology of History, 2, 185–219. (In Russian)
  • Russel, B. (1959). History of Western Philosophy. Rus. Ed. Moscow: Izdatel’stvo Inostrannoi Literatury Publ. (In Russian)
  • Sokolowski, R. (1984). Intentional Analysis and the Noema. Dialectica, 38 (2/3), 113–129.